Decision Under Risk
February 27, 2024
In this lecture we will illustrate the concept of measurment using as an example measurement of risk aversion
Introduce the concept of choice under risk
Define measures of risk aversion
Construct behavioural measures
Discuss the relationship between behavioural measures and survey measures
In many economic situations, decisions are made under risky or uncertain conditions
Utility framework under certainty to be extended to account for decision under risk or uncertainty
What are plausible requirements for this?
In many cases the outcome is money, so we restrict the view over utility over money. This is not innocuous as has been shown, as money does not give utility when one receives it.
Prototypical economists conception of human behaviour
\[ \max{x_i^t\in X_i}\sum_{t=0}^{\infty}\delta^t\sum_{s_t\in S_t}p(s_t)U(x_i^t|s_t) \]
What does it take for \(p(s_t)\) to be rational beliefs?
Having subjective probabilities that obey law of probability
Motivational story by Savage (1954)
A businessman contemplates buying a certain piece of property. He considers the outcome of the next presidential election relevant. So, to clarify the matter to himself, he asks whether he would buy if he knew that the Democratic candidate were going to win, and decides that he would. Similarly, he considers whether he would buy if he knew that the Republican candidate were going to win, and again finds that he would. Seeing that he would buy in either event, he decides that he should buy, even though he does not know which event obtains, or will obtain, as we would ordinarily say. It is all too seldom that a decision can be arrived at on the basis of this principle, but except possibly for the assumption of simple ordering, I know of no other extra-logical principle governing decisions that finds such ready acceptance.
If \(\alpha \succ \beta\) if you knew that \(E\) occurred, and same if you knew that NOT \(E\) occurred, then you should \(\alpha \succ \beta\) regardless.
Probability and Sure principle imply expected utility theory, so we can write:
\[ U(x)=\sum_{s \in S} u(x,s)=\sum_{s\in S} u(x) p(s) \]
Preferences over lotteries (q,r,s) can be represented by a utility function with the EU form \[EU= \sum_{\in I} p_i U(q_i)\] Preferences satisfy
Relates the value of a convex function of a sum (integral) to the sum (integral) of the convex function
If \(w\) is a random variable \(U(w)\) is
Given that the curvature of the utility function one can think of coarser measures of risk aversion
{Arrow–Pratt measure of absolute risk-aversion (ARA)}
\[ A(x)=-\frac{u''(x)}{u'(x)} \]
{Arrow-Pratt-De Finetti measure of relative risk-aversion (RRA)}
\[ R(x)=xA(x)=-\frac{x\cdot u''(x)}{u'(x)} \]
In the case of CARA, ARA must be constant
\[ A(x)=-\frac{u''(x)}{u'(x)} = cons. \]
one can show that this leads to a utility fuction of the following form:
\[ u(x) = -e^{-\theta x} \]
In the case of CRRA, RRA must be constant
\[ R(x)=xA(x)=-\frac{x\cdot u''(x)}{u'(x)} = cons. \]
one can show that this leads to a utility fuction of the following form:
\[ u(x)= \begin{cases} \frac{1}{1-\theta}x^{1-\theta} & \mathsf{ if } \quad \theta>0 \mathsf{\quad and\quad } \theta \neq 1 \\ \ln x & \mathsf{ if } \quad \theta =1 \end{cases} \]
Standard-gamble methods | |
---|---|
1. Preference comparison | \(x_{1p} x_2 \text{ versus } x_c\) |
2. Probability equivalence | \(x_{1} \underline{p} x_2 \sim x_c\) |
3. Value equivalence | \(\underline{x}_{1p} x_2 \sim x_c\) |
4. Certainty equivalence | \(x_{1p} x_2 \sim \underline{x_c}\) |
Paired-gamble methods | |
5. Preference comparison | \(x_{1p} x_2 \text{ versus } x'_{1p} x'_2\) |
6. Probability equivalence | \(x_{1\underline{p}} x_2 \sim x'_1p x'_2\) |
7. Value equivalence | \(\underline{x}*{1p} x_2* \sim x'{1p} x'_2\) |
[Standard Gamble] Compare sure amount with non-degenerate lottery
[Paired Gamble] Compare two non-degenerate lotteries
[Probability equivalence] Elicit that makes subject indifferent
[Certainty equivalence] Elicit that makes subject indifferent
Under EU both methods are equivalent
{Direct question} What amount of money, Eur , if paid to you with certainty, would make you indifferent to the lottery paying Eur ,(x_1) with probability (p) and Eur ,(x_2) with probability (1 - p).
Bisection procedure
Bracketing procedure
Trade-off precision and chaining}
if error propagation is an issue, bracketing should be preferred
if precision is a concern, bisection should be chosen
\[ p[(x_{A1} - x_{A2}) - (x_{B1} - x_{B2})] + (x_{A2} - x_{B2} ) \]
falls with (p) and is negative for \[ p > (x_{A2} - x_{B2} )/[(x_{B1} - x_{B2}) (x_{A1} - x_{A2} )] \]
risk-neutral individual switches from option A to option B when \[ p > (x_{A2} - x_{B2} )/[(x_{B1} - x_{B2} ) - (x_{A1} - x_{A2} )] \]. Switch point reveals risk attitude.
The Table shows the choices that the subjects face when (x_{A1} = 2), (x_{A2} = 1.6), (x_{B1} = 3.85 )and (x_{B2} = 5). %Subjects who switch from A to B between choices 4 and 5 are risk-neutral, while those %who switch between choices 2 and 3 are significantly risk-seeking and those switching %between choices 7 and 10 are significantly risk-averse.
Strength of eliciting indifferences allows direct estimation of individual relative risk aversion based on a particular utility function. Consider, constant relative risk-aversion (CRRA) utility function,
\[ u(x) = \begin{cases} x^{1-\theta}/(1-\theta) & \text{\, if\, } \theta \neq 1 \\ log(x) & \text{\, if\, } \theta = 1 \end{cases} \]
Shape of individual utility can be inferred from subject’s choices
EU maximiser with risk-aversion parameter \(\theta\) indifferent if \(\ldots\)
\[ p \times 21- \theta + (1 - p) \times 1.6 1-\theta = p \times 3.851-\theta + (1 - p) \times 51-\theta \]
Solving for \(\theta\) yields degree of risk aversion as a function of the probability \(p\) at which a subject switches between options A and B.
Precision: Not clear, where the subject’s preference lies in this interval: the subject may be slightly risk-averse, slightly risk-seeking or risk neutral.
Paired Lottery Choice
Choose one of
Choice (50/50 Gamble) | Low payoff | High payoff | Expected return | Standard deviation | Implied CRRA range |
---|---|---|---|---|---|
Gamble 1 | 28 | 28 | 28 | 0 | \(3.46 < r\) |
Gamble 2 | 24 | 36 | 30 | 6 | \(1.16 < r < 3.46\) |
Gamble 3 | 20 | 44 | 32 | 12 | \(0.71 < r < 1.16\) |
Gamble 4 | 16 | 52 | 34 | 18 | \(0.50 < r < 0.71\) |
Gamble 5 | 12 | 60 | 36 | 24 | \(0 < r < 0.50\) |
Gamble 6 | 2 | 70 | 36 | 34 | \(r < 0\) |
German Socio Economic Panel (GSOEP)
Please tell me, in general, how willing or unwilling you are to take risks. Please use a scale from 0 to 10, where 0 means you are ”completely unwilling to take risks” and a 10 means you are ”very willing to take risks”. You can also use any numbers between 0 and 10 to indicate where you fall on the scale, like 0, 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7, 8, 9, 10.
Dohmen et al., 2011 find a correlation coefficient between multiple price list method and question: \(0.4079\)
(Lejuez et al., 2002)
Intuitive task to measure risk preferences without the usual numerical representation of lotteries
Bracketing procedure
Decision rule parametrised by CRRA preference parameter ()
\(DR_j(\theta) = U(A_j|\theta)-U(B_j|\theta)\) predicts choices of A and B
Individuals make decision error ()
DM chooses \(A_j\) over option \(B_j\) if \(DR_j(\theta)+\epsilon_j > 0\)
Contradicts deterministic decision rule, if error large enough